Have you seen a White Raven?

Dom Fisherman
4 min readMay 19, 2023

The Raven Paradox

https://www.saanichnews.com/wp-content/uploads/2021/06/25474492_web1_210616-PQN-White-Raven-Parents-whiteraven_1.jpg

The Raven Paradox is a famous example of the difficulties and limitations of inductive reasoning, which is the process by which we generalize from specific facts. It was initially proposed by the philosopher Carl Gustav Hempel in the 1940s and has since sparked significant discussion and controversy.

The Raven Paradox is essentially a confirmation paradox: the concept that confirming examples of a hypothesis do not appear to have the same logical weight as disconfirming occurrences. Consider the following premise to better comprehend the paradox: “All ravens are black.” Observing black ravens confirms this theory. However, we can corroborate this idea by witnessing non-black non-ravens such as white shoes, red fruits, or blue vehicles, according to the contradiction.

This is because observing a non-black non-raven and discovering that it is not a counterexample to the hypothesis implicitly validates the hypothesis since it is evidence that supports the hypothesis by removing one of the potential counterexamples. This form of confirmation, however, is illogical, as we would not ordinarily consider witnessing non-black non-ravens as proof for the claim that all ravens are black.

Examples and Stories

https://pbs.twimg.com/media/C0xxxCaXEAAQYTH.jpg

The narrative of astronomer Arthur Eddington will help you better appreciate the conundrum. Eddington organized an expedition in 1919 to witness a total solar eclipse and put Einstein’s theory of general relativity to the test. The gravity of big objects like the sun, according to the hypothesis, bends light, causing the apparent location of stars near the sun to alter during an eclipse.

This phenomena was noticed by Eddington, who validated Einstein’s hitherto unproven hypothesis. However, the theory’s confirmation was indirect, since it resulted from the lack of a prediction made by a competing theory rather than from direct evidence in favor of Einstein’s theory. In other words, Eddington implicitly proved Einstein’s theory by removing a potential counterexample by examining the locations of stars that were not eclipsed by the sun during the eclipse.

This case shows the challenges of validating hypotheses as well as the limitations of inductive reasoning. While it may be tempting to draw broad conclusions from individual findings, doing so is riddled with ambiguity and potential inaccuracies. It is critical to identify the possibilities of other explanations and to be open to the possibility that future data will disprove a theory.

https://jonathanweisberg.org/vip/_main_files/figure-html/gruebleengraph-1.png

The narrative of the philosopher Nelson Goodman, who established the idea of grue to demonstrate the limitations of induction, is another example that provides insight on the contradiction. The color “grue,” according to Goodman, refers to objects that are green if noticed before a specific period and blue if observed beyond that time. The concept of grue calls into question the notion that we may draw generalizations from observations since it implies that the categories we use to generate these generalizations are arbitrary and context-dependent.

Goodman’s concept of grue stresses the importance of being conscious of our generalizations’ assumptions and boundaries. It is simple to fall into the trap of believing that a pattern seen in the past will continue to hold in the future or that the categories we use to organize items are intrinsically significant. However, doing so can lead to inaccuracies and oversimplifications that impair our capacity to comprehend the world around us.

Inductive deduction, despite its challenges and restrictions, is a vital technique for formulating predictions and forming conclusions based on specific observations. However, it is critical to be aware of this process’s potential weaknesses as well as approach it with skepticism and humility.

https://cdnb.artstation.com/p/assets/images/images/040/667/595/large/brandon-yu-crime-and-punishment-3.jpg?1629541197

In his work “Crime and Punishment,” Dostoevsky investigates the boundaries of inductive thinking via the figure of Porfiry Petrovich, a detective who solves murders using a combination of deductive and inductive reasoning. Porfiry’s method is looking for patterns and generalizations in specific circumstances, such as watching dubious conduct and developing conclusions based on it.

However as the tale goes on, it becomes obvious that Porfiry’s strategy is wrong. His reliance on inductive reasoning causes him to ignore crucial information and make often incorrect inferences. Raskolnikov, the primary protagonist, utilizes rational thought to figure out the crime in the end. This illustration emphasizes the limitations of inductive reasoning and the significance of taking into account alternate theories and methods.

Conclusion

https://unsplash.com/photos/dnUSau5fYQo

Finally, the Raven Paradox serves as a timely reminder of the difficulties and limitations of inductive reasoning. It emphasizes the paradoxical nature of confirmation through non-black non-ravens, as well as the dangers of extrapolating generalizations from individual data. Despite its shortcomings, inductive reasoning is nonetheless a useful method for generating predictions and forming conclusions. It is critical to approach the process with skepticism and humility, acknowledging the possibility of other explanations and being conscious of our generalizations’ assumptions and limits. By doing so, we may better traverse the intricacies of our surroundings and avoid the inaccuracies and oversimplifications that might impede our comprehension.

--

--

Dom Fisherman

Author | Existentialist | Human. I write about philosophy, psychology, short stories, and life experiences.